home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- $Unique_ID{bob00784}
- $Pretitle{}
- $Title{History Of Religions
- Chapter II}
- $Subtitle{}
- $Author{Foot Moore, George}
- $Affiliation{}
- $Subject{confucius
- heaven
- nature
- mencius
- religion
- chu
- philosophy
- state
- death
- life}
- $Date{1913}
- $Log{}
- Title: History Of Religions
- Book: Religions Of China
- Author: Foot Moore, George
- Date: 1913
-
- Chapter II
-
- Moral And Political Philosophy
-
- Confucius - His Career - Attitude Toward Religion - Gods and Spirits -
- Heaven - Ethics - Conflicting Doctrines - Yang Chu and Moh Tih - Mencius -
- Political Theory - Wang Ch'ung - Neoconfucianism: Chou Tun-i and Chu Hi -
- Religious Aspects of the Sung Philosophy.
-
- The orthodox religion of China, the religion of the state with all its
- officials and of the whole literate class, is by Western scholars commonly
- called Confucianism. ^1 The name must not, however, be understood to import
- that Confucius stands to this religion in the same relation in which Buddha
- stands to Buddhism or Mohammed to Mohammedanism. Confucius was not the
- founder of a religion, nor even a reformer in the ordinary sense of the word.
- In no sphere is his own estimate of himself, "a transmitter, not a maker,
- believing in and loving the ancients," truer than in that of religion; and
- nothing could have seemed to him, with his exaggerated veneration of
- antiquity, more irreligious than any innovations in the ceremonies that were
- instituted in the most remote times by the model sovereigns, Yao and Shun, and
- had been piously observed by all their worthy successors. His utmost thought
- was to revive customs that had fallen into desuetude and to conform everything
- to the ancient pattern. This was part of his general plan for the restoration
- of the good old times; but it does not appear that he had much opportunity to
- achieve practical results in this direction, nor were his efforts to inspire
- in his stiff-necked generation the reverence for Heaven and its decrees, which
- was the inwardness of the old religion, much more fruitful. The religion
- which has left its monuments in the oldest hymns of the Shi-king as well as in
- the documents of the Shu-king, as it has been described above, is
- substantially the religion of Confucius and of modern official China.
-
- [Footnote 1: The Chinese name is Ju-kiau, "School of the Learned."]
-
- In another sense, however, it is not improper that it should bear his
- name. For Confucius has been through more than twenty centuries in China the
- great authority in religion as well as in ethics and politics; the entire body
- of canonical and classical literature is attributed to him as editor or
- author; the whole education of China has been in this literature, and almost
- bounded by it and works based upon it. Furthermore, Confucius unquestionably
- impressed on his disciples the non-committal, and in some respects agnostic,
- disposition toward theological questions which was characteristic of his own
- temper; and in the later Confucian schools, especially in the renaissance of
- philosophy under the Sung dynasty, this tendency is still more strongly
- marked. On the other hand, though Confucius was no more original in the field
- of ethics than of religion, he and his successors, the authors of the Great
- Learning, the Doctrine of Mean, the Book of Filial Piety, and above all
- Mencius, gave to Chinese ethics classical form and authoritative finality.
-
- Confucius was born in 551 B. C., in the little state of Lu, within the
- bounds of the present province of Shan-tung. Of his early life almost nothing
- is known; but he had at least such opportunities of education that at
- twenty-two he began to teach. It may be assumed that in the following years,
- while giving instruction to the pupils who in increasing numbers resorted to
- him, he continued his own studies of history, literature, and ancient customs
- (especially ritual, in which he early acquired the reputation of an expert),
- and at thirty, he tells us, he "stood firm," that is, had settled opinions.
-
- An incident of considerable importance in his life was a visit, in 517 B.
- C., to Loh-yang, the capital of the empire, where he had a long-desired
- opportunity to see the places where the great sacrifices to Heaven and Earth
- were offered, and to inspect all the arrangements of the ancestral temple of
- the reigning dynasty of Chou and of the imperial court, and perhaps to pursue
- researches in the archives. The following years were a period of great
- disorder in the state of Lu. At the beginning of it, in 517, Confucius
- followed his exiled sovereign to the neighbouring state of Ts'i; but, finding
- the then ruling duke little disposed to profit by his counsels, soon returned
- to his native country, where he kept steadfastly aloof from the strife of
- factions, declining public employment. In this period, probably, fall the
- collecting and editing of the ancient literature with which his name is
- inseparably connected. In the year 501, however, he was appointed chief
- magistrate of a city named Chung-tu, and put his theories of administration
- into practice with such effect, we are told, that in a twelvemonth Chung-tu
- was a model town. This transformation was noted with surprise by the duke,
- who asked Confucius whether the same principles could be applied to the
- government of a state, and being assured that they could, he made Confucius
- assistant superintendent of public works, and shortly after minister of
- justice; whereupon, according to his eulogistic biographers, laws against
- crime fell into disuse, because there were no criminals.
-
- He strengthened the ducal house and weakened the private families. He
- exalted the sovereign and depressed the ministers; a transforming government
- went abroad. Dishonesty and dissoluteness were ashamed, and hid their heads.
- Loyalty and good faith became the characteristics of the men, and chastity and
- docility of the women. Strangers came in crowds from other states. Confucius
- became the idol of the people, and flew in songs through their mouths.
-
- But this Utopian Lu excited the jealous apprehensions of its neighbours,
- and by liberal presents of horses and dancing-girls they distracted the
- ruler's mind from the counsels of the sage, who, finding himself disprized,
- surrendered his office, and sadly - and slowly, hoping that the duke might at
- last repent - shook the dust of the ungrateful state from his feet. Thus
- ended Confucius' one brief experience as a practical statesman. For thirteen
- years, accompanied by a band of disciples, he wandered from court to court,
- offering his counsel and exhortations to princes and ministers; sometimes
- consulted by them, but not establishing any permanent influence; yet never
- losing confidence that if one of them would but employ him, "I would effect
- something considerable in the course of twelve months, and in three years the
- government would be perfected." In 483 he was recalled to Lu, where he spent
- the last years of his life in labours upon the ancient literature,
- particularly the Shiking, in finishing the Ch'un-ts'iu, and in the study of
- Yih-king, of which he is reported to have said, "If some years were added to
- my life, I would give fifty to the Yih, and then I might come to be without
- grave faults." He died in 478 B.C., at the age of seventy-three years.
-
- In all the externals of religion Confucius was extremely punctilious. As
- a child, we are told, his favourite play was arranging sacrificial vessels and
- practising postures of ceremony; and as a man he showed the same predilections
- by antiquarian researches into the ritual of former dynasties. The apparatus
- of worship at the capital drew from him the exclamation, "Now I know the
- wisdom of the Duke of Chou, and how the house of Chou attained to the imperial
- sway." The ancient music of Shun, the tradition of which was preserved in
- Ts'i, so ravished him that for the three months he did not know the taste of
- flesh: "I did not know," he said, "that music could be made so excellent as
- this." He believed that the virtue of the people and the welfare of the state
- depended upon the reverent observance of the sacrifices to the gods and the
- spirits of the ancestors. He himself "sacrificed to the dead as if they were
- present; he sacrificed to the spirits as if the spirits were present"; and the
- crowning proof to him that the Duke of Lu was incorrigible was the indecorous
- haste with which he despatched the solemn sacrifice to Heaven in order to
- hurry back to his dissolute pleasures.
-
- Confucius, who was never weary of discussing the minutest points of
- ritual, had very little to say about more vital religious matters. Too much
- stress has perhaps been laid by Legge and others upon particular utterances,
- such as his reply to a disciple who asked him about serving the spirits of the
- dead: "While you are not able to serve men, how can you serve the spirits." "I
- venture to ask about death," the inquirer continued: "So long as you do not
- know life, how can you know about death?" To another, who asked what wisdom
- is, he answered: "To give one's self earnestly to the duties due to men, and,
- while respecting spiritual beings, to keep aloof from them." It is not so much
- single sayings of this kind as the absence of any teaching about the nature of
- these "spiritual beings" and their relations to men that is significant.
-
- The belief that the destiny of states and individuals is ordained by
- Heaven was accepted by Confucius without question. Faith in his own mission
- sustained him in critical moments of his life. When his life was threatened
- in K'uang, he said: "After the death of King Wen, was not the cause of truth
- lodged here in me? If Heaven had wished this cause of truth to perish, then
- I, a feeble mortal, should not have got into such a relation to that cause.
- While Heaven does not let the cause of truth perish, what can the people of
- K'uang do to me?" Yet one of the subjects on which he seldom spoke was the
- appointments of Heaven. He scarcely ever uses the name Shang-ti, Supreme
- Lord, and it has been surmised that he consciously avoided it because it more
- distinctly implied the personality of God, preferring the impersonal, or at
- least ambiguous, T'ien, Heaven. Here, again, the inference is uncertain.
- T'ien occurs with increasing relative frequency in the later hymns of the
- Shi-king and the later documents of the Shu-king; and Confucius may well have
- employed it in conformity with the prevalent usage of his times, rather than
- from any prejudice of his own.
-
- Confucius was not a speculative thinker; the problems of the origin of
- the universe, the nature of being, the one and the many, which exercised the
- early philosophers of Greece and India, lay beyond the horizon of his mind.
- His common-sense philosophy dealt exclusively with the practical questions of
- ethics and politics. To him, as to other thinkers of this type, God was
- essentially the moral order of the world, an order energising in the phenomena
- of nature as well as in the course of history and the destiny of individual
- lives. The more uniform, that is, the more unvaryingly moral, this order is,
- in the interest of ethics, conceived to be, the more impersonal the conception
- becomes - the something, not ourselves, that makes for righteousness. If in
- the unvarying moral order the destiny of men is determined in strict
- accordance with their conduct, it is obviously futile to importune Heaven to
- change it: "He who offends against Heaven has none to whom he can pray." Once
- when Confucius was ill his disciple, Tsze-lu, asked leave to pray for him. He
- said, "Is that proper?" Tsze-lu replied: "Yes. In the Prayers it is said,
- 'Prayers has been made to the spirits of the upper and lower worlds.'" The
- Master said, "It must be a long time since I prayed."
-
- Expressions which imply a more personal thought of God are, however, not
- lacking in the sayings of Confucius. "Heaven produced the virtue that is in
- me. Huan T'ui - what can he do to me?" "The Master said, 'Alas! there is no
- one that knows me.' Tsze-kung said, 'What do you mean by thus saying that no
- one knows you?' The Master replied, 'I do not murmur against Heaven. I do not
- grumble against men. My studies lie low, and my penetration rises high. But
- there is Heaven; that knows me.'" Such language shows that Confucius' ethical
- rationalism was not incompatible with a real religious faith.
-
- In the ethics of Confucius filial piety is, as it has been in China in
- all ages, the cardinal virtue. The son who loves, respects, and obeys his
- father, anticipating his wishes while he lives and regarding them when he is
- dead, will make a kind brother, a sincere friend, and a loyal subject; men who
- are filial and fraternal seldom offend against their superiors. Beyond the
- "five relations" of the family and the state are the relations of men to their
- fellows in society, and these are to be ruled by the same principle. Filial
- piety and fraternal love are the root of benevolence, which Confucius defined
- as love to all men.
-
- The one word "reciprocity" may serve as a rule of practice for a man's
- whole life: "What you do not want done to yourself do not do to others."
- Benevolence must not, however, transgress the limits of equity. When asked
- what he would say about the principle enounced by his older contemporary,
- Lao-tse, that injury should be requited with kindness, Confucius'
- characteristics answer was: "With what, then, will you requite kindness?
- Requite injury with justice, and kindness with kindness." Men should deal with
- one another as Heaven deals with men, according to their deserts. If the duty
- of blood vengeance for the murder of a father or mother devolve upon a son, he
- should sleep on straw, with his shield for a pillow and his weapon at hand,
- "he must be determined not to live with the slayer under the same heaven."
-
- A fundamental doctrine of the Confucian ethics is that the nature of man
- is good. In the Shu-king, T'ang says: "The Most High Lord has conferred even
- on the inferior people a moral sense, by obeying which they obtain a nature
- constantly right." "Heaven, in giving birth to the multitudes of the people,
- annexed to every faculty and relationship its law. The people possess this
- normal nature, and they consequently love its normal virtue." In this respect
- all men are similarly endowed. Hence if men do wrong, they cannot lay the
- responsibility on the nature which Heaven has given them.
-
- But though all are good at the beginning, few prove themselves to be so
- at the end. Through parental neglect to inculcate filial piety, through
- faulty education and bad example, the most deteriorate, and by habit
- unrighteousness becomes second nature. The good nature bestowed by Heaven
- must be developed into a stable good character by man's own effort. To
- achieve this it is necessary to have not only the steadfast will but the true
- ideal. It is the end of education to set forth this ideal and inspire men to
- strive after it. Accordingly, the burden of Confucius' teaching is the
- character of the "superior man" - the man who in every situation knows the
- right thing and does it, a man not only of faultless virtues, but of faultless
- propriety.
-
- The age of Confucius and the two following centuries were a time of great
- intellectual activity in China; conflicting theories of ethics were enunciated
- and controversy was rife. Yang Chu, who lived about the middle of the fourth
- century, was a pessimist. Life is short and full of trouble; death is the end
- of all. The only profit in this evil world is to enjoy the pleasures of sense
- while we can, without sacrificing a hair to the interests of mankind or the
- welfare of the state, and regardless of the praise or blame of men. None is
- more famous than Shun and Yu, Chou-kung and Confucius. Those heroes of virtue
- never had a day's enjoyment in their lives; and though their fame endure ten
- thousand generations, what is that to them? The dead know nothing of the
- praises bestowed upon them; they are no better than a stock or a lump of clay.
- None is more infamous than Kieh and Chou; yet those tyrants in their lifetime
- enjoyed to the full riches, power, and honour, and what do they care now for
- the curses of posterity? The ancients knew this, and followed their natural
- inclinations; they did not make a virtue of denying themselves the pleasures
- that came in their way, nor let themselves be urged by ambition for fame to
- put constraint on their natures.
-
- At the opposite extreme from this cynical egoism is the radical altruism
- of Moh Tih. One who inquires into the cause of the ills of society and the
- state as a physician inquires into the cause of a disease will find that all
- those ills have one origin: men of every class and condition love themselves
- and do not love their fellows; hence they wrong others for their own
- advantage. There is therefore but one remedy - mutual love. For if men loved
- one another as every man loves himself, there would be no more crime. If each
- regarded his neighbour's house as his own, who would then steal? If each
- regarded his neighbour's person as his own, who, then, would rob? If princes
- regarded foreign states as their own, where would there be occasion for wars?
- All the misery in the world - the overpowering of the weak by the strong, the
- oppression of the minority by the majority, the defrauding of the simple by
- the shrewd, the haughtiness of the eminent toward the insignificant - is due
- to the making of distinctions between men, whereas universal love embraces
- them all, without making such differences. If it is asked how this millennium
- is to be brought about, Moh Tih answers, with characteristic Chinese faith in
- the influence of the ruler, that if princes would only show that they
- delighted in the love of all for all, the people infallibly would cultivate
- it.
-
- The teachings of both Yang Chu and Moh Tih are vigorously combated by
- Mencius. The individualism of the former - "every man for himself" - is
- anarchism; the altruism of the latter - "love all men equally" - is unfilial:
- both strike at the roots of human society. If they should prevail, they would
- reduce men to the state of the beasts, who acknowledge neither king nor
- father; benevolence and righteousness would cease, and men would devour one
- another. If this is to be averted, these false doctrines must be stopped, and
- the sound principles of Confucius reaffirmed.
-
- The Confucian doctrine of the inborn goodness of human nature was
- impugned by more than one philosopher. One affirmed that the nature of man is
- morally indifferent; it is like water, which will run in whatever direction a
- channel is opened for it. Others maintained that it can be made good or bad
- by influences from without, as in the times of the good kings Wen and Wu the
- people loved goodness, and under the cruel kings Yu and Li they loved cruelty.
- Others, again, that the nature of some is good, and of others bad; a virtuous
- father may have a wicked son, or the converse. Against all these Mencius
- argues. From the sentiments which are proper to human nature it is evident
- that it is constituted for the practice of what is good; this is what is meant
- by saying that man's nature is good. Such feelings, common to all men, are
- sympathy and pity, shame and abhorrence, respect and reverence, approbation
- and disapprobation. From these spring benevolence, righteousness, propriety,
- and knowledge, which are therefore not implanted but innate; only we do not
- think of them. Hence it is said: "Strive for them, and you will attain them;
- neglect them, and you will lose them."
-
- The controversy continued. Siun K'uang, a younger contemporary of
- Mencius, maintained in opposition to him that man's nature is evil. His
- spontaneous impulses are all selfish: the hungry man is prompted by nature
- simply to satisfy his appetite; if out of consideration for the rights and
- interests of others he resists this impulse, it is by a conscious effort and
- because he has been taught that he ought to do so - not therefore by nature,
- but against natural impulses. Uncontrolled by education and moral discipline
- or by the law and its penalties, there would be a state of universal strife -
- every man's hand would be against his neighbour. That man has to strive to
- become good is proof that his nature is evil. A later philosopher, Yang Hiung
- (53 B. C. - 18 A.D.), took an intermediate position: human nature is a mixture
- of good and evil; he who cultivates the good side of his nature becomes a good
- man, and he who cultivates the evil a bad man. In the end, however, chiefly
- through the influence of Mencius, the native goodness of man became the
- orthodox dogma, which is to-day laid down as a fundamental proposition in
- every elementary text-book of moral instruction.
-
- To the exposition and defence of Confucianism against opposing doctrines
- no one contributed so much as Mencius, who thus earned the place he has long
- held next in honour to the Master. Mencius was born in 372 B.C., and died in
- 289. He seems never to have held office, and, unlike Confucius, it does not
- appear that he sought to do so. Like many others in his day, he passed from
- city to city, teaching the disciples who followed him in his migrations or who
- in any place resorted to him, expounding to rulers, as occasion offered, the
- enlightened principles of government on which the prosperity of states
- depends, and giving sound advice on the ethics of private life and the conduct
- of affairs, as a kind of consulting philosopher to princes, after the manner
- of the wandering sophists among the Greeks. His works, consisting largely of
- such discussions, surpass the Confucian Analects in logical acumen and in
- orderly presentation. He employs the form of dialogue with much skill to
- refute an opponent or to constrain assent to his own proposition by
- superiority in dialectic in a fashion which at times reminds us of Socrates.
-
- A Chinese scholar, comparing Mencius with Confucius, said: "Confucius
- spoke only of benevolence, but as soon as Mencius opens his mouth we hear of
- benevolence and righteousness. Confucius spoke of the will or mind, but
- Mencius enlarged also on the nourishment of the passion-nature" - the
- cultivation of the emotions. ^1 In the conversation with Hui of Liang, with
- which the book begins, the prince salutes the philosopher:
-
- [Footnote 1: See Mencius, II, 1, 2, 9 ff.]
-
- "Venerable sir, since you have not counted it far to come here, a
- distance of a thousand li, may I presume that you are likewise provided with
- counsels to profit my kingdom?" Mencius replied: "Why must your majesty speak
- of profit? There are benevolence and righteousness, and these should suffice.
- If your majesty say, 'What can I do to profit my kingdom?' the great officers
- will say, 'What can we do to profit our families?' and the inferior officers
- and the common people will say, 'What can we do to profit ourselves?'
- Superiors and inferiors will try to snatch this profit the one from the other,
- and the state will be endangered. . . . There never has been a man trained to
- benevolence who neglected his parents; there never has been a man trained to
- righteousness who made his sovereign an after consideration. Let your majesty
- say: 'Benevolence and righteousness, and these only.' Why must you use that
- word 'profit'?" ^1
-
- [Footnote 1: Mencius, I, cf. VI, 2, 4.]
-
- The state exists for the people, and its stability depends on the welfare
- of the people. The conditions of public welfare are ultimately economic. The
- government must preserve peace abroad and order at home; it must not burden
- the people with forced labour on public works by which they are withdrawn from
- their fields, nor harass them with a complicated system of taxes and imposts;
- it must instruct, encourage, and, if necessary, assist the tillers of the
- soil, for on agriculture the prosperity of all depends. To reduce the people
- to starvation by misgovernment or neglect is sheer murder.
-
- "If the people have not a certain livelihood, they will not have a fixed
- heart. And if they have not a fixed heart, there is nothing which they will
- not do in the way of self-abandonment, of moral deflection, of depravity, and
- of wild license. When they thus have been involved in crime, to follow them
- up and punish them - this is to entrap the people. Therefore an intelligent
- ruler will regulate the livelihood of the people, so as to make sure that,
- above, they have sufficient wherewith to serve their parents, and, below,
- sufficient wherewith to support their wives and children; that in good years
- they shall always be abundantly satisfied, and that in bad years they shall
- escape the danger of perishing. After this he may urge them,and they will
- proceed to what is good, for in this case the people will follow after that
- with ease."
-
- In the contrary case, "in good years their lives are continually
- embittered, and in bad years they do not escape perishing. In such
- circumstances they only try to save themselves from death, and are afraid they
- will not succeed. What leisure have they to cultivate propriety and
- righteousness?" ^2
-
- [Footnote 2: Mencius, I, 1, 7, 20.]
-
- This insistence on the economic conditions not only of prosperity, but,
- consequently, of righteousness and good order, is characteristic of Mencius;
- and he discusses at large the practical measures by which the end is to be
- achieved.
-
- Vox populi, vox dei - "Heaven sees as my people sees; Heaven hears as my
- people hears." The common voice of the people about a man's character, his
- fitness for office, or his desert of death, is more to be trusted than the
- advice of courtiers or high officials.
-
- Mencius explicitly asserts the right of revolution: "If a prince have
- grave faults," he told a king to his face, "the nobles and ministers who are
- of his blood ought to remonstrate with him, and if he do not listen to them
- after they have done so again and again, they ought to dethrone him." The
- murder of a tyrant like Chou was not the putting to death of a sovereign, but
- the cutting off of a base fellow; by his crimes he had forfeited all right to
- a better name than ruffian and robber or to different treatment. But only a
- "minister of Heaven" may presume thus to execute its requirements.
-
- Wang Ch'ung, who wrote toward the end of the first century of our era,
- occupies in some respects a place apart in the history of Chinese thought. ^1
- He may be described as a materialistic monist, and his physical philosophy
- somewhat resembles that of Epicurus and Lucretius. At the beginning there was
- a homogeneous vaporous or nebulous chaos. Out of this the lighter and the
- heavier elements "spontaneously" - that is, without intelligence or design -
- separated; the warm and light (elemental fire) above, the cold and dark,
- represented by water, below. So he adapts the old doctrines of Yang and Yin,
- fortifying himself by quotations from the Yih-king and the Li-ki. The Taoist
- Lieh-tsze developed a similar theory; but Wang Ch'ung, as pure materialist,
- has no use for the mystical Tao nor for the primal intelligence of Chu Hi and
- the Sung Confucianists. From the combination and spontaneous interaction of
- these principles all things arise. Man's body is of coarse matter, Yin; his
- vital spirit and intelligence are of the fiery nature of the Yang. Heaven -
- that is, the sky - is material just as truly as the earth, only of a different
- composition, and its operations are equally without design. It does not take
- note of men's doings to punish the bad and reward the good. Heaven does not
- speak, nor does it hear what men say; divination is absurd - how can the shell
- of a dead tortoise or the stalks of a withered weed elicit a response from
- Heaven! "Some people think that Heaven produces grain for the purpose of
- feeding mankind, and silk and hemp to clothe them. That would make Heaven
- man's farmer or mulberry-girl!" The philosopher is fond of pricking man's
- self-importance. To this vast frame of nature we are no more than insects
- crawling on a human body. The struggle for existence is proof that there is
- no wise and good purpose in creation. "If Heaven had produced its creatures
- on purpose, it ought to have taught them to love one another, and not to prey
- upon and destroy one another" - precisely the argument of Epicurus.
-
- [Footnote 1: See A. Forke, Lun-Heng: Philosophical Essays of Wang Ch'ung.
- 1907.]
-
- The vital spirit, or soul, is a particle of the cosmic principle of
- warmth and light; it is born with the body, grows and decays with it, and at
- death returns to its source. It is an individual soul endowed with
- intelligence and activity only through its union with the body. There is no
- consciousness before birth and none after death. If souls were immortal, they
- would give some sign of their existence. He combats the notion that the dead
- become ghosts and can harm men. Ghosts are not the spirits of the dead, they
- are the creatures of morbid fancy. "When sick people are haunted by fears,
- ghosts appear; their fears set their imaginations to work, and their eyes have
- visions." By dispelling these beliefs, he, like Lucretius, would deliver men
- from the fears to which they are in bondage.
-
- Sacrifices are useless; there are no personal beings such as people
- imagine to enjoy them, nor can the spirits do anything for man or against him.
- At most, offerings are symbolical acts expressing the gratitude and piety of
- the offerer; but no evil consequence can follow from omitting them. Exorcism
- is equally unprofitable; the spirits cannot harm man; and if they could, they
- certainly would not let themselves be driven away, but would resent the
- attempt and would make it the worse for the exorcist.
-
- In his ethics Wang Ch'ung does not depart so widely from the current
- doctrine. On the much-debated question of the native goodness of man he holds
- that some are good and some bad, just as some are intelligent and some stupid.
- Good fortune is not the reward of virtue, nor misfortune the punishment of
- vice; both depend on fate. "Profound philosophy does not procure riches, and
- the highest accomplishments do not get a man into office."
-
- Not the least striking pages in these essays are those in which the
- author roundly denies that the former times, whose praises everybody sang,
- were better than the present. This superstition is of a piece with the notion
- that in antiquity people were all tall and strong, good-looking and
- long-lived, while nowadays they are little and ugly, feeble and short-lived.
- Human nature has been the same in all ages; there were unprincipled characters
- in the past and there are to-day men of the keenest sense of honour. Wang
- Ch'ung has no reverence for his predecessors because of their antiquity. He
- has an essay on Taoist untruths, and is particularly hard on the political
- theories of Han-fei; but he freely criticises Confucius and Mencius, whose
- authority their followers did not dare to question, pointing out obscurities
- and contradictions in their teachings.
-
- In the following centuries Confucian orthodoxy prevailed, and became as
- stagnant as undisputed orthodoxies are wont to be. The great expansion of
- Buddhism falls in this period, and what thinking was done in China for a
- thousand years was chiefly done in Buddhist monasteries, and on metaphysical
- and theological questions with which Confucianism had never concerned itself.
- In the eleventh and twelfth centuries of our era, however, in the brilliant
- renaissance of all branches of literature, new life was breathed into the dry
- bones of philosophy. Buddhism had been reduced to low estate by the great
- persecution under the emperor Wu Tsung (in the middle of the ninth century)
- and by a succession of repressive measures under later rulers; it was,
- moreover, intellectually in decadence. Taoism had long since degenerated into
- magical quackery. The field was clear for a revival of Confucianism. The
- revival could, however, not be a mere repristination of the teachings of
- Confucius and Mencius. Taoism and Buddhism had raised metaphysical problems
- which never entered into the mind of those worthies, but which, when once they
- were raised, could not be ignored.
-
- The founder of the Neoconfucianism of the Sung dynasty, or, as it called
- itself, Sing-li, Philosophy of Nature, was Chou Tun-i (1017-1073 A. D.). His
- system is based on the Yih-king, whose occult meaning he was, according to Chu
- Hi, the first to fathom. From our point of view his significance lies in the
- fact that he endeavoured to transcend the dualism of Chinese cosmic philosophy
- with its two forces, Yin and Yang, whose reciprocal operation explained the
- universe and all its phenomena, by positing a "Great Ultimate," or first
- principle, from which both proceed - a species of monism. The Ultimate in
- motion generates the Yang, or active principle, at rest, the Yin, or passive
- principle, and this alternation repeats itself eternally, motion tending to
- rest and rest passing over again into motion, "each is the cause of the
- other." Yang and Yin coming together generate the five elements and the five
- corresponding meteorological phenomena, and the four seasons begin their
- rotation. The male and female principles are evolved, and generate all
- things. Man occupies the highest place in nature, being of a more spiritual
- constitution. By contact with the world, the five cardinal virtues are called
- into action; good and evil are discriminated; different types of conduct
- emerge. The virtuous man governs himself by moderation, straightforwardness,
- humanity, and righteousness, and thus realises the idea of manhood.
- Cultivating his character, the virtuous man is happy, while the common man,
- living in conflict with it, is unhappy.
-
- The greatest name in the Confucian revival is Chu Hi (1130-1200 A. D.).
- His recension of the classical texts and his interpretation of them in his
- commentaries became authoritative, and his manuals of domestic rites and of
- morals and manners, chiefly based on the Li-ki, have done more, perhaps, than
- any other books to educate the Chinese people in correct Confucian conduct and
- ceremonial. In his philosophy he called himself a disciple of Chou Tun-i, but
- he departed from the teaching of that thinker in some important particulars.
- Chu Hi finds in the universe two principles, a primal matter (K'i) and an
- incorporeal immanent intelligence which he identifies with the Ultimate of
- Chou-tsze. Both are eternal, so that it cannot be said that intelligence is
- prior in time, but only that it is logically prior, as in rank it is superior.
- The Ultimate is not a being existing independently before heaven and earth; it
- is only a comprehensive name for the rational principle in heaven and earth
- and all things. In the terms of Western philosophy, matter and form are
- correlative; there is no pure form without matter, as there is no matter
- without form. Chu Hi's relation to Chou-tsze is therefore somewhat like that
- of the Stoics to Aristotle, as, indeed, the Sing-li philosophy has many other
- resemblances to Stoic physics. The Yang and the Yin, active and passive, warm
- and cold, light and dark, are modes of matter, whence proceed the five
- elements and all sensible objects. Humanity, righteousness, moral ideals, and
- wisdom are qualities of the rational principle.
-
- Western critics often call this philosophy materialistic; but inasmuch as
- Chu Hi's eternal matter is informed and directed by an immanent intelligence,
- it is evident that Neoconfucianism is a materialism only in the sense in which
- Stoicism may be called a cosmological materialism. Indeed, the name is in one
- sense less properly applicable to it than to Stoicism, since for Chu Hi the
- immanent intelligence is incorporeal. With atomistic mechanical materialism
- such as Epicureanism and the Indian system of the Carvakas it has no affinity,
- and as little with the modern materialistic monism which makes mind a function
- of matter. In fact, like Stoicism, it might with quite as much propriety be
- called pantheism.
-
- It has been remarked that Confucius, in speaking of God, avoids
- anthropomorphic expressions, and hardly ever uses even the title Shang-ti. Chu
- Hi explicitly rejects the notion of a Heavenly Emperor, with ministers on
- either hand like an earthly monarch; and it is obvious that his philosophy has
- no place for a sovereign of the universe ruling it from without. Concerning
- death Confucius preserved an agnostic reticence - when you do not know about
- life, how can you know about death? Chu Hi, like the sensualist Yang Chu and
- the materialist Wang Ch'ung, though from different premises, denies a
- conscious existence after death.
-
- It is not strange that, on the ground of these negations, Neoconfucianism
- has been declared essentially irreligious by those to whom belief in a
- personal God and the immortality of the soul are the essence of religion.
- There is no question, however, that it has been the religion of multitudes of
- scholars in China, and its introduction into Japan in the seventeenth century
- greatly quickened the religious interest of thinking men. Its conception of
- the "infinite and eternal Power which is not ourselves, and yet constitutes
- the very essence of our being," has been thus defined: "It is not God - that
- is, an individual like a man; it is not material, it is not dynamic, it is not
- like our passions, nor like our knowledge, nor like our spirit or mind or
- soul; it cannot be described in terms of cause and effect; it preceded even
- the negative and positive principles by whose interaction the universe has
- been formed. Formless, from it has come all form; powerless, from it has come
- all power; it remains through all change changeless, and yet is norm and
- governor of it all. This supreme, which we cannot yet call object, nameless
- and adjectiveless, may yet be best defined by that which stirs in the soul of
- man as righteousness." ^1
-
- [Footnote 1: G. W. Knox, Development of Religion in Japan, pp. 176 f.]
-
-